Julian Barbour - The End of Time - The Next Revolution in Physics

Здесь есть возможность читать онлайн «Julian Barbour - The End of Time - The Next Revolution in Physics» весь текст электронной книги совершенно бесплатно (целиком полную версию без сокращений). В некоторых случаях можно слушать аудио, скачать через торрент в формате fb2 и присутствует краткое содержание. Год выпуска: 2001, Издательство: Oxford University Press, Жанр: Физика, на английском языке. Описание произведения, (предисловие) а так же отзывы посетителей доступны на портале библиотеки ЛибКат.

The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics: краткое содержание, описание и аннотация

Предлагаем к чтению аннотацию, описание, краткое содержание или предисловие (зависит от того, что написал сам автор книги «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics»). Если вы не нашли необходимую информацию о книге — напишите в комментариях, мы постараемся отыскать её.

Two views of the world clashed at the dawn of thought. In the great debate between the earliest Greek philosophers, Heraclitus argued for perpetual change, but Parmenides maintained there was neither time nor motion. Over the ages, few thinkers have taken Parmenides seriously, but I shall argue that Heraclitan flux, depicted nowhere more dramatically than in Turner’s painting below, may well be nothing but a well-founded illusion. I shall take you to a prospect of the end of time. In fact, you see it in Turner’s painting, which is static and has not changed since he painted it. It is an illusion of flux. Modern physics is beginning to suggest that all the motions of the whole universe are a similar illusion – that in this respect Nature is an even more consummate artist than Turner. This is the story of my book.
Richard Feynman once quipped that "Time is what happens when nothing else does." But Julian Barbour disagrees: if nothing happened, if nothing changed, then time would stop. For time is nothing but change. It is change that we perceive occurring all around us, not time. Put simply, time does not exist. In this highly provocative volume, Barbour presents the basic evidence for a timeless universe, and shows why we still experience the world as intensely temporal. It is a book that strikes at the heart of modern physics. It casts doubt on Einstein's greatest contribution, the spacetime continuum, but also points to the solution of one of the great paradoxes of modern science, the chasm between classical and quantum physics. Indeed, Barbour argues that the holy grail of physicists--the unification of Einstein's general relativity with quantum mechanics--may well spell the end of time. Barbour writes with remarkable clarity as he ranges from the ancient philosophers Heraclitus and Parmenides, through the giants of science Galileo, Newton, and Einstein, to the work of the contemporary physicists John Wheeler, Roger Penrose, and Steven Hawking. Along the way he treats us to enticing glimpses of some of the mysteries of the universe, and presents intriguing ideas about multiple worlds, time travel, immortality, and, above all, the illusion of motion. The End of Time is a vibrantly written and revolutionary book. It turns our understanding of reality inside-out.

The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics — читать онлайн бесплатно полную книгу (весь текст) целиком

Ниже представлен текст книги, разбитый по страницам. Система сохранения места последней прочитанной страницы, позволяет с удобством читать онлайн бесплатно книгу «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics», без необходимости каждый раз заново искать на чём Вы остановились. Поставьте закладку, и сможете в любой момент перейти на страницу, на которой закончили чтение.

Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Actually, there are two mists because the wave function, being complex, contains two numbers, which are its two components . I shall call them the red mist and green mist , respectively. I shall also introduce a third number, calling it the blue mist . The intensity of this third mist is determined by the two primary components as the sum of the squares of the red and green intensities. This is the mist mentioned in the early chapters. Those in the know will recognize the three mists as the real and imaginary parts of the wave function and the square of its amplitude.

The prominence that I give to these mists could be regarded by most theoretical physicists (above all Dirac and Heisenberg, were they still alive) as a one-sided, if not to say distorted and naive picture of quantum mechanics. The mists (as opposed to things called operators) are not particularly appropriate for talking about most quantum experiments currently performed in laboratories. However, the experiment I have in mind is not done in a laboratory. It is what the universe does to the instants of time. For this experiment, the one that really counts, I think the language of mists is appropriate. Those who disagree might have second thoughts if they really started to think of how inertial frames and duration arise. I come back to these issues later.

I shall now give, in familiar space-time terms, a quantum-mechanical account of the two-slit experiment (Figure 35). At an initial time, the wave function associated with a particle is in a ‘cloud’ well to the left of the barrier. Inside the cloud, ψ is not zero. Outside, it is zero. As time passes, this cloud moves to the right and, in general, changes its shape. It evolves (in accordance with some definite rules). Typically, it ‘spreads’. At the barrier, some of the cloud is reflected back to the left but some passes through the two slits. Initially there are two separate clouds, but they spread rapidly if the slits are narrow, and soon overlap. Characteristic wave interference occurs. Thus, when the merged wave reaches the screen, ψ is not the same everywhere, and fringes can form. In fact, the best fringes are formed by a steady ‘stream’ of wave function, not a cloud.

INTERPRETING THE WAVE FUNCTION

The question now arises: where will the particle in Figure 35 be observed? The answer, given already by the German physicist Max Born in 1926, is that ψ determines, through the intensity of the blue mist, the probability of where the particle will be observed. The blue mist enables you to guess where the particle will ‘hit’ – twice the intensity means twice the probability.

There are many mysteries in quantum mechanics, and the first is the probabilities. We can send identical clouds through the slits many times. The fringe patterns are always exactly reproduced, but the hits are distributed randomly. Only after many ‘runs’ does a pattern of hits build up. The blue mist gives that pattern. Where its intensity is high, many hits occur; where it is low, few; where it is zero, none. Quantum mechanics determines these probabilities perfectly, but says nothing about where the individual hits will occur.

Figure 35A cloud of wave function ψ approaching two slits at t 0 and t - фото 37

Figure 35.A ‘cloud’ of wave function ψ approaching two slits (at t = 0 and t = 1), passing through them, dividing into two (at t = 2), spreading and overlapping (t = 3) and impinging on a screen (t = 4).

Einstein found this decidedly disturbing. He could not believe that God reaches for a die every time physicists set up such an experiment and force the particle to show up somewhere. For that is what standard quantum mechanics implies – brute chance determines outcomes. But there are even more puzzling things. It is worth saying that quantum mechanics has a remarkably beautiful and self-contained structure. Examined mathematically, it is a very harmonious whole. It is hard to see how its structure could be modified naturally to make it determine where individual hits occur, especially when relativity is taken into account.

The next mystery is the collapse of the wave function . Just before the particle hits the screen, its ψ can be spread out over a large region. What happens to ψ when the particle is suddenly found somewhere? The standard answer is that the wave is instantaneously annihilated everywhere except where the particle is now known to be.

If we want to determine what now happens, we have to start afresh from a small, reduced cloud. The large cloud has been ‘collapsed’ and has no more relevance. This too provokes much puzzling, especially for those (like Schrödinger in 1926) who would wish to think of ψ as something real, a density of charge, say. How can something real disappear instantaneously? Nothing in the equations describes the collapse – it is simply postulated. Lawful evolution, in accordance with the rules (equations) of quantum mechanics, continues until an observation is made, but then the rules are simply set aside. Quite different rules apply in measurements , as they are called. (In quantum mechanics, the term ‘measurement’ is used a very precise way. It means that some definite arrangement of instruments is used to establish the value of some physical property – say the speed or position of a particle.) The abrupt and schizophrenic change of the rules when measurements are made is a major part of the notorious measurement problem . There are rules for evolution and rules for measurement – and they are even more different than chalk and cheese. Nevertheless, both are excellently confirmed, though we have to be careful when saying that the collapse is instantaneous, and even when it occurs.

STATES WITHIN STATES

Just as mysterious as the rule change when measurements are made is a certain mutual exclusivity about the kinds of measurement that can be made. So far, I have talked only about particle positions. However, we can also measure other quantities – for example, a particle’s energy, momentum or angular momentum. It is particularly fascinating that information about them all is coded at once in ψ. This is another big difference from classical mechanics.

Imagine a perfect sinusoidal wave that extends with constant wavelength from infinity to infinity. For the moment, suppose that it is ‘frozen’, like the wave patterns you see in damp sand at low tide. Let me call this the red wave, because it represents the red mist. Now imagine another identical though green wave, shifted forward by a quarter of a wavelength relative to the red wave (Figure 36). Then the red peaks lie exactly at the green wave’s nodes, where the green wave has zero intensity. As time passes, the red and green waves move to the right, maintaining always their special relative positioning. A wave function in this special form represents a particle that has a definite momentum: if it hit something, it would transmit a definite impulse to it. A particle with the opposite momentum is represented similarly, but travels in the opposite direction and has the green peaks a quarter of the wavelength behind the red peaks. According to the quantum rules, the particle has a definite momentum because its ψ has a definite wavelength and is perfectly sinusoidal. Such wave functions give the best interference effects in two-slit experiments. They are called momentum eigenstates . (The German word eigen means ‘proper’ or ‘characteristic’.)

Figure 36The wave function of a particle with a definite momentum The - фото 38

Читать дальше
Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Похожие книги на «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics»

Представляем Вашему вниманию похожие книги на «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics» списком для выбора. Мы отобрали схожую по названию и смыслу литературу в надежде предоставить читателям больше вариантов отыскать новые, интересные, ещё непрочитанные произведения.


Отзывы о книге «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics»

Обсуждение, отзывы о книге «The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics» и просто собственные мнения читателей. Оставьте ваши комментарии, напишите, что Вы думаете о произведении, его смысле или главных героях. Укажите что конкретно понравилось, а что нет, и почему Вы так считаете.

x