• Пожаловаться

Martin Heidegger: The Metaphysics of German Idealism

Здесь есть возможность читать онлайн «Martin Heidegger: The Metaphysics of German Idealism» — ознакомительный отрывок электронной книги совершенно бесплатно, а после прочтения отрывка купить полную версию. В некоторых случаях присутствует краткое содержание. категория: unrecognised / на английском языке. Описание произведения, (предисловие) а так же отзывы посетителей доступны на портале. Библиотека «Либ Кат» — LibCat.ru создана для любителей полистать хорошую книжку и предлагает широкий выбор жанров:

любовные романы фантастика и фэнтези приключения детективы и триллеры эротика документальные научные юмористические анекдоты о бизнесе проза детские сказки о религиии новинки православные старинные про компьютеры программирование на английском домоводство поэзия

Выбрав категорию по душе Вы сможете найти действительно стоящие книги и насладиться погружением в мир воображения, прочувствовать переживания героев или узнать для себя что-то новое, совершить внутреннее открытие. Подробная информация для ознакомления по текущему запросу представлена ниже:

Martin Heidegger The Metaphysics of German Idealism

The Metaphysics of German Idealism: краткое содержание, описание и аннотация

Предлагаем к чтению аннотацию, описание, краткое содержание или предисловие (зависит от того, что написал сам автор книги «The Metaphysics of German Idealism»). Если вы не нашли необходимую информацию о книге — напишите в комментариях, мы постараемся отыскать её.

This volume comprises the lecture course that Heidegger gave in 1941 on the metaphysics of German Idealism. The first part of the lecture course contains a preliminary consideration of the distinction between ground and existence. The elucidation of the conceptual history includes a striking confrontation with Kierkegaard’s and Jaspers’ concepts of existence, as well as an elucidation of the concept of existence in , which Heidegger distinguishes from the former concepts. Heidegger’s self-interpretation is not an end in itself, however, but rather a way of pointing to Schelling’s distinction between ground and existence, whose root and inner necessity and whose various versions Heidegger discusses subsequently. The second part of the lecture course is focused on Schelling’s “freedom treatise,” which Heidegger regards as the pinnacle of the metaphysics of German Idealism. Heidegger’s consideration of Schelling’s distinction between ground and existence finds its guiding thread in the introduction of the realms of being – eternal or finite, each being is a joining of the ground of existence and existence itself. In a subsequent overview, Heidegger discusses the relation of the distinction between ground and existence to the essence of human freedom and to the essence of the human. On the basis of this discussion, it becomes possible to grasp the connection between freedom and evil in Schelling’s system. This important work by Heidegger, published here in English for the first time, will be of great interest to students and scholars of philosophy and to anyone interested in Heidegger’s work.

Martin Heidegger: другие книги автора


Кто написал The Metaphysics of German Idealism? Узнайте фамилию, как зовут автора книги и список всех его произведений по сериям.

The Metaphysics of German Idealism — читать онлайн ознакомительный отрывок

Ниже представлен текст книги, разбитый по страницам. Система сохранения места последней прочитанной страницы, позволяет с удобством читать онлайн бесплатно книгу «The Metaphysics of German Idealism», без необходимости каждый раз заново искать на чём Вы остановились. Поставьте закладку, и сможете в любой момент перейти на страницу, на которой закончили чтение.

Тёмная тема

Шрифт:

Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

3

But from where else can a necessity come to us? If we could reckon this necessity up for ourselves of our own accord, as it were, it would, then, not be a necessity that compelled us. Are there, then, mysterious experiences in play, which destine us to persevere with thought and to awaken a thinking which questions? This can suffice least of all in the realm of thought; here, cold audacity alone has the word. But this, too, is again only an assertion, which, moreover, takes it to be already decided that we are actually placed into a necessity to think. We appear thus again, only in another direction, to rush ahead endlessly on the path of misgivings. And is it not by now already clear that misgivings { Bedenken } most of all hinder us from thinking { Denken }?

Then, as a point of fact , everything hinges precisely on “making” a beginning in thought without having any misgivings. But should we then still engage with “the historiographic” at all? If not, where should we begin? How insignificant the aforementioned misgivings – regarding the restriction to a particular text of a single thinker – now seem in relation to the objection that, in reflecting on the metaphysics of German Idealism, we are already running after something past and “orienting” ourselves “historiographically.” This sort of orientation contains, after all, the admission that philosophy would only be the historiographical making-present of its past, which it admittedly must be when it no longer finds “a measure or rule” in itself. Schelling expressed himself clearly enough on this matter in the final paragraph of his Freedom Treatise (415): 2

If the dialectical principle, that is, the understanding which is differentiating but thereby organically ordering and shaping things in conjunction with the archetype by which it steers itself, is withdrawn from philosophy so that philosophy no longer has in itself either measure or rule, then nothing else is left to philosophy but to seek to orient itself historiographically and to take the tradition as its source and plumb line […]. Then it is time, as one intended to ground our poetry through acquaintance with the literature of all nations, to seek for philosophy a historical norm and foundation as well.

4

But Schelling turns against this time and says:

The time of merely historiographical faith is past, if the possibility of immediate cognition is given. We have an older revelation than any written one – nature. (Ibid.)

Yet does this hold straight away for our time as well? Or is this time – our time – a different one? Which law, then, requires that thinking conform to its time? Or is thinking untimely, and indeed always and necessarily so? But how could this be the case, if the untimely were but the inversion of the timely – a still fiercer dependence on “time” { “Zeit” }? In accordance with what should “an age” { “Zeitalter” } be determined in order for it to be definitive for a thinking? But how, if essential thinking first decides an age in what is most proper to it, and does so without this age having or being able to have a public consciousness of its own historical essence? But then this decisive thinking must in turn be so originary that it cannot lose itself to a past epoch, so as to reckon up from this epoch what is necessary for the present, making what is necessary conform with the present. That reckoning up is the essence of “historicism”; and this making-conform is the essence of “currentism” { “Aktualismus” }. Both belong together. They are the sometimes overt, sometimes covert enemies of decisive thinking (see § 5).

5

If, however, as our undertaking suggests, we do not abandon the historical reflection on the metaphysics of German Idealism – but perhaps first introduce it, in fact, and thereby nevertheless act only from the one necessity { Notwendigkeit } to think in the sense of essential thinking – then that is a sign that our necessities are different, different because the need { Not } has become a different one. Or is it perhaps even the same need, not the need of an age, not the need of a century, but the need of two millennia, the need arising from the fact that, ever since then, thinking has been “metaphysics”? Perhaps this need has meanwhile become more pressing, which does not preclude that it has become even less visible. Indeed, our thinking, when it attempts to reflect on German Idealism historically, is not a historiographic orientation; but neither is it “immediate cognition” in the manner of the metaphysics of German Idealism. The thinking that has become necessary is a historical thinking. An actual attempt should clarify what this means.

We will therefore now leave all misgivings about our undertaking to the side; we will, however, attend to how they resolve and sort themselves out in due course. For a long time to come, we will perhaps not be able to distinguish historiographic explanation from historical thinking. Yet this we shall keep in mind, namely, that the historical thinking attempted here can be subsumed neither under philosophicalhistoriographic explanation nor under “systematic” reflection, nor under a mixture of both. It suffices if we glean from what has been said, even if only in broad strokes, the manner in which we do not arbitrarily and blindly take up Schelling’s treatise so as to publicize it for erudite ends.

Several tools of the trade are necessary for the work of interpretation. But all this remains obtuse if we do not question and think from out of what presses and determines us, no matter how confused all this may be, and how beset it may be with habits of thought that have converged from often unknown sources and impetuses.

6

§ 3 Elucidations of the Title of the Treatise

Schelling’s treatise bears the title: “Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom and the Matters Connected Therewith.” It appeared in the year 1809 as the final part of a collection of investigations that Schelling had already published earlier and that were selected from the totality of his existing publications in order to serve as an introduction to the “Freedom Treatise.”

Cite the four preceding parts (do not at first go into the “works” and biography):

1 Of the I as Principle of Philosophy, or, On the Unconditional in Human Knowledge (1795)

2 Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism (1795)

3 Treatises on the Elucidation of the Idealism of the Doctrine of Science (1796–1797)

4 On the Relation of the Fine Arts to Nature: An Academic Speech (1807)

The text of the Freedom Treatise will be cited according to volume and page numbers of the edition of Schelling’s Sämtliche Werke , 1856–1861, fourteen volumes. 3The Freedom Treatise can be found in volume VII, pp. 336–416. These page numbers are printed on the inner margin of the edition of the Philosophische Bibliothek . 4

7

The title of the treatise: philosophical investigations: “ philosophical?zētēsis ; “ freedom ”: arbitrary topic? freedom of the will? Kant; “ human ”: essence of the human; “ essence ”: inner possibility (formal concept) and ground of actuality ( centrum ), 5the absolute; “ and {…} therewith ”: with the “essence” (that is, with the absolute); “ connected ”: nexus – sustasissystem ; “ matters ” { Gegenstände }: (formally) what stands {steht} ‘there’ in such a standing-together (system) ; “ the ”: not a few – arbitrary ones, but, rather, eminent ones.

Читать дальше
Тёмная тема

Шрифт:

Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Похожие книги на «The Metaphysics of German Idealism»

Представляем Вашему вниманию похожие книги на «The Metaphysics of German Idealism» списком для выбора. Мы отобрали схожую по названию и смыслу литературу в надежде предоставить читателям больше вариантов отыскать новые, интересные, ещё не прочитанные произведения.


Отзывы о книге «The Metaphysics of German Idealism»

Обсуждение, отзывы о книге «The Metaphysics of German Idealism» и просто собственные мнения читателей. Оставьте ваши комментарии, напишите, что Вы думаете о произведении, его смысле или главных героях. Укажите что конкретно понравилось, а что нет, и почему Вы так считаете.