Bruce Mesquita - Prediction - How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory

Здесь есть возможность читать онлайн «Bruce Mesquita - Prediction - How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory» весь текст электронной книги совершенно бесплатно (целиком полную версию без сокращений). В некоторых случаях можно слушать аудио, скачать через торрент в формате fb2 и присутствует краткое содержание. Год выпуска: 2011, Издательство: Random House, Жанр: Старинная литература, на английском языке. Описание произведения, (предисловие) а так же отзывы посетителей доступны на портале библиотеки ЛибКат.

Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory: краткое содержание, описание и аннотация

Предлагаем к чтению аннотацию, описание, краткое содержание или предисловие (зависит от того, что написал сам автор книги «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory»). Если вы не нашли необходимую информацию о книге — напишите в комментариях, мы постараемся отыскать её.

Bruce Bueno de Mesquita can predict the future.
From international terrorism to corporate fraud, from climate change to the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita has been predicting the future for decades. Using Game Theory (a theory based on the rationale that everyone acts in their own self-interest) he can foretell and even engineer events. His forecasts, for everyone from the CIA to major international companies, have an extraordinary 90% success rate.
In this fascinating and immensely readable book he explains how you can use Game Theory to your own advantage - to win a legal dispute, advance your career and even get the best possible price for your car. Prediction will change your understanding of the world - both now and in the future.

Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory — читать онлайн бесплатно полную книгу (весь текст) целиком

Ниже представлен текст книги, разбитый по страницам. Система сохранения места последней прочитанной страницы, позволяет с удобством читать онлайн бесплатно книгу «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory», без необходимости каждый раз заново искать на чём Вы остановились. Поставьте закладку, и сможете в любой момент перейти на страницу, на которой закончили чтение.

Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

3

картинка 7

GAME THEORY 102

GAME THEORY 101 started us off thinking about how different people are from particles. In short, we are strategists. We calculate before we interact. And with 101 under our belts, we know enough to delve more closely into the subtleties of strategizing.

Of the many lessons game theory teaches us, one of particular import is that the future—or at least its anticipation—can cause the past, perhaps even more often than the past causes the future. Sound crazy? Ask yourself, do Christmas tree sales cause Christmas? This sort of reverse causality is fundamental to how game theorists work through problems to anticipate outcomes. It is very different from conventional linear thinking. Let me offer an example where failing to recognize how the future shapes the past can lead to really bad consequences.

Many believe that arms races cause war. 1With that conviction in mind, policy makers vigorously pursue arms control agreements to improve the prospects of peace. To be sure, controlling arms means that if there is war, fewer people are killed and less property is destroyed. That is certainly a good thing, but that is not why people advocate arms control. They want to make war less likely. But reducing the amount or lethality of arms just does not do that.

The standard account of how arms races cause war involves what game theorists call a hand wave—that is, at some point the analyst waves his hands in the air instead of providing the logical connection from argument to conclusions. The arms-race hand wave goes like this:

When a country builds up its arms it makes its adversaries fear that their security is at risk. In response, they build up their own arms to defend themselves. The other side looks at that buildup—seeing their own as purely defensive—and tries to protect itself by developing still more and better weapons. Eventually the arms race produces a massive overcapacity to kill and destroy. Remember how many times over the U.S. and Soviet nuclear arsenals could destroy the world! So, as the level of arms—ten thousand nuclear-tipped missiles, for instance—grows out of proportion to the threat, things spiral out of control (that’s the hand wave— why do things spiral out of control? ), and war starts.

Wait a moment, let’s slow down and think about that. The argument boils down to claiming that when the costs of war get to be really big—arms are out of proportion to the threat—war becomes more likely. That’s really odd. Common sense and basic economics teach us that when the cost of anything goes up, we generally buy less, not more. Why should that be any less true of war?

True, just about every war has been preceded by a buildup in weapons, but that is not the relevant observation. It is akin to looking at a baseball player’s positive test for steroids as proof that he cheats. What we want to know is how often the acquisition of lots more weapons leads to war, not how often wars are preceded by the purchase of arms. The answer to the question we care about is, not very often .

By looking at wars and then asking whether there had been an arms race, we confuse cause and effect. We ignore all the instances in which arms may successfully deter fighting exactly because the anticipated destruction is so high. Big wars are very rare precisely because when we expect high costs we look for ways to compromise. That, for instance, is why the 1962 Cuban Missile Crisis ended peacefully. That is why every major crisis between the United States and the Soviet Union throughout the cold war ended without the initiation of a hot war. The fear of nuclear annihilation kept it cold. That is why lots of events that could have ignited world wars ended peacefully and are now all but forgotten.

So, in war and especially in peace, reverse causality is at work. When policy makers turn to arms control deals, thinking they are promoting peace, they are taking much bigger risks than they seem to realize. Failing to think about reverse causation leads to poor predictions of what is likely to happen, and that can lead to dangerous decisions and even to catastrophic war.

We will see many more instances of this kind of reasoning in later chapters. We will examine, for example, why most corporate fraud probably is not sparked by executive greed and why treaties to control greenhouse gas emissions may not be the best way to fight global warning. Each example reinforces the idea that correlation is not causation. They also remind us that the logic of reverse causation—called endogeneity in game theory—means that what we actually “observe”—such as arms races followed by war—are often biased samples.

The fact that decisions can be altered by the expectation of their consequences has lots of implications. In Game Theory 101 we talked about bluffing. Working out when promises or threats should be taken seriously and when they are (in game-theory-speak) “cheap talk” is fundamental to solving complicated situations in business, in politics, and in our daily encounters. Sorting out when promises or threats are sincere and when they are just talk is the problem of determining whether commitments are credible.

LET’S PLAY GAMES

In predicting and engineering the future, part of getting things right is working out what stands in the way of this or that particular outcome. Even after pots of money are won at cards, or hands are shaken and contracts or treaties are signed, we can’t be sure of what will actually get implemented. We always have to ask about commitments. Deals and promises, however sincerely made, can unravel for lots of reasons. Economists have come up with a superbly descriptive label for a problem in enforcing contracts. They ask, is the contract “renegotiation-proof”? 2This question is at the heart of litigiousness in the United States.

I once worked on a lawsuit involving two power companies. One produced excess electricity and sold it to a different electric company in another state. As it happened, the price for electricity shot way up after the contract was signed. The contract called for delivery at an agreed-upon lower price. The power seller stopped delivering the promised electricity to the buyer, demanding more money for it. Naturally, the buyer objected, pointing out that the contract did not provide for changing the price just because market conditions changed. That was a risk that the buyer and seller agreed to take when they signed their contract. Still, the seller refused to deliver electricity. The seller was sued and defended itself vigorously so that legal costs racked up on both sides. All the while that bitter accusations flew back and forth, the seller kept offering to make a new deal with the plaintiff. The deal involved renegotiating their contract to make adjustments for extreme changes in market prices. The plaintiff resisted, always pointing—rightly—to the contract. But the plaintiff also really needed the electricity and couldn’t get it anywhere else for a better price than the seller, my client, was willing to take—and my client knew that. Eventually, the cost of not providing the necessary electricity to their own clients became so great that the plaintiff caved in and took the deal they were offered.

Here was nasty, avaricious human nature hard at work in just the way game theorists think about it. Yes, there was a contract, and its terms were clear enough, but the cost of fighting to enforce the contract became too great. However much the plaintiff declared its intent to fight the case in court, the defendant knew it was bluffing. The plaintiff’s need for electricity and the cost of battling the case out in court were greater than the cost of accepting a new deal. And so it was clear that the terms of the contract were not renegotiation-proof. The original deal was set aside and a new one was struck. The original deal really was not a firm commitment to sell (or probably, for that matter, to buy) electricity at a specified price over a specified time period when the market price moved markedly from the price stipulated in the agreement. Justice gave way, as it so often does in our judicial system, to the relative ability of plaintiffs and defendants to endure pain.

Читать дальше
Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Похожие книги на «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory»

Представляем Вашему вниманию похожие книги на «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory» списком для выбора. Мы отобрали схожую по названию и смыслу литературу в надежде предоставить читателям больше вариантов отыскать новые, интересные, ещё непрочитанные произведения.


Отзывы о книге «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory»

Обсуждение, отзывы о книге «Prediction: How to See and Shape the Future with Game Theory» и просто собственные мнения читателей. Оставьте ваши комментарии, напишите, что Вы думаете о произведении, его смысле или главных героях. Укажите что конкретно понравилось, а что нет, и почему Вы так считаете.

x