P. M. S. Hacker - Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience

Здесь есть возможность читать онлайн «P. M. S. Hacker - Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience» — ознакомительный отрывок электронной книги совершенно бесплатно, а после прочтения отрывка купить полную версию. В некоторых случаях можно слушать аудио, скачать через торрент в формате fb2 и присутствует краткое содержание. Жанр: unrecognised, на английском языке. Описание произведения, (предисловие) а так же отзывы посетителей доступны на портале библиотеки ЛибКат.

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience: краткое содержание, описание и аннотация

Предлагаем к чтению аннотацию, описание, краткое содержание или предисловие (зависит от того, что написал сам автор книги «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience»). Если вы не нашли необходимую информацию о книге — напишите в комментариях, мы постараемся отыскать её.

The second edition of the seminal work in the field—revised, updated, and extended  In 
 M.R. Bennett and P.M.S. Hacker outline and address the conceptual confusions encountered in various neuroscientific and psychological theories. The result of a collaboration between an esteemed philosopher and a distinguished neuroscientist, this remarkable volume presents an interdisciplinary critique of many of the neuroscientific and psychological foundations of modern cognitive neuroscience. The authors point out conceptual entanglements in a broad range of major neuroscientific and psychological theories—including those of such neuroscientists as Blakemore, Crick, Damasio, Dehaene, Edelman, Gazzaniga, Kandel, Kosslyn, LeDoux, Libet, Penrose, Posner, Raichle and Tononi, as well as psychologists such as Baar, Frith, Glynn, Gregory, William James, Weiskrantz, and biologists such as Dawkins, Humphreys, and Young. Confusions arising from the work of philosophers such as Dennett, Chalmers, Churchland, Nagel and Searle are subjected to detailed criticism. These criticisms are complemented by constructive analyses of the major cognitive, cogitative, emotional and volitional attributes that lie at the heart of cognitive neuroscientific research. 
Now in its second edition, this groundbreaking work has been exhaustively revised and updated to address current issues and critiques. New discussions offer insight into functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), the notions of information and representation, conflict monitoring and the executive, minimal states of consciousness, integrated information theory and global workspace theory. The authors also reply to criticisms of the fundamental arguments posed in the first edition, defending their conclusions regarding mereological fallacy, the necessity of distinguishing between empirical and conceptual questions, the mind-body problem, and more. Essential as both a comprehensive reference work and as an up-to-date critical review of cognitive neuroscience, this landmark volume: 
Provides a scientifically and philosophically informed survey of the conceptual problems in a wide variety of neuroscientific theories Offers a clear and accessible presentation of the subject, minimizing the use of complex philosophical and scientific jargon Discusses how the ways the brain relates to the mind affect the intelligibility of neuroscientific research Includes fresh insights on mind-body and mind-brain relations, and on the relation between the notion of person and human being Features more than 100 new pages and a wealth of additional diagrams, charts, and tables Continuing to challenge and educate readers like no other book on the subject, the second edition of 
 is required reading not only for neuroscientists, psychologists, and philosophers, but also for academics, researchers, and students involved in the study of the mind and consciousness.

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience — читать онлайн ознакомительный отрывок

Ниже представлен текст книги, разбитый по страницам. Система сохранения места последней прочитанной страницы, позволяет с удобством читать онлайн бесплатно книгу «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience», без необходимости каждый раз заново искать на чём Вы остановились. Поставьте закладку, и сможете в любой момент перейти на страницу, на которой закончили чтение.

Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Herophilus

The revolutionary writings of Herophilus (325–255 bc) are now lost, so knowledge of his discoveries on the nervous system are due to later authors, especially Galen (130–210 ad) who placed Herophilus as the most prominent among his forebears, commenting that Herophilus ‘increased anatomical theory the most’ 17for ‘the neuroanatomical knowledge of the brain remained scanty until Herophilus performed his dissections’. 18These dissections confirmed Aristotle’ s distinction between the cerebrum and the cerebellum 19and revealed the nature of the ventricles, including the fourth ventricle of the cerebellum. 20But perhaps most importantly Herophilus identified nerves and their emergence from the brain and spinal cord, for, as Galen records, Herophilus holds that ‘all the nerves throughout the body below the head grow either from the cerebellum (parenkephalis) or from the spinal marrow’. 21Herophilus also distinguished between purposive (motor) and sensory nerves, probably because of his extensive vivisection, and followed the optic nerve from the brain to the eye. 22On the other hand, Herophilus failed to distinguish between nerves on the one hand and tendons/ligaments on the other, considering these to be the terminal extensions of the nerves in muscles. 23It was not until the beginning of the twentieth century that the ending of nerves in muscle, at the synapse formed by the neuromuscular junction, was finally resolved. 24

Galen: motor and sensory centres

It was Galen who apprehended that nerves arising from the brain and spinal cord are necessary conduits for initiation of muscle contraction. The Aristotelian account was changed accordingly. Vital pneuma was held to be delivered by blood vessels to the brain and converted to psychic pneuma (whose composition was unclear), whence it was conducted along the nerves to the muscles. Thus, ‘The nerves which in consequence enjoy the role of conduits, carry to the muscles the forces that they draw from the brain as from a source.’ 25This allowed the muscles to contract, probably as a consequence of their ballooning as they filled with the psychic pneuma . 26

Galen distinguished motor from sensory nerves

Hence Galen introduced the idea of motor nerves derived from the spinal cord. 27As a consequence of his observations on injured chariot drivers, he also distinguished sensory from motor nerves . These were differentiated in terms of their relative ‘hardness’, motor nerves being ‘hard’ and sensory nerves ‘soft’. 28The hard motor nerves were uniquely associated with their origins in the spinal cord, the soft sensory nerves with the brain. 29

Using the term ‘soul’ in an Aristotelian sense, Galen argued that there was a ‘motor soul’ and a ‘sensory soul’, which were not to be considered as two different entities but as two different functions or principles of activity. 30According to this conception, and given the assumed relationship between the relative hardness/softness of nerves, the motor/sensory differentiation and the fact that the hardest nerves are found uniquely associated with the spinal cord (caudal), the idea of two separate souls or principles of activity, one associated with the spinal cord and one with the brain is natural (although it is unlikely that Galen succumbed to this temptation). It was to have considerable vogue in the eighteenth century to explain the existence of continuing spinal cord reflexes in decorticate animals. However, by then the conception of the soul (the anima ) had changed and had become entwined with that of consciousness.

Galen: the functional localizationof the rational soul in the ventricles

This association of the pure sensory nerves with the brain, and the fact that these nerves were very soft, carried with it important implications for brain function. 31It is clear that Galen associated the whole brain, and not just the ventricles, with the mental capacities of humans. In On the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body he states: ‘In those commentaries I have given the demonstrations proving that the rational soul is lodged in the enkephalon; that this is the part with which we reason; that a very large quantity of psychic pneuma is contained in it; and that this pneuma acquires its own special quality from elaboration in the enkephalon’ (‘enkephalon’ is a cognate of ‘enkephalos’, meaning ‘that which is in the head’). So Galen attributed to the brain those functions in perception that Aristotle had attributed to the heart. However, this did not distinguish between the respective roles of the cortex and the ventricles. Galen did not ascribe to the cortex any special function with regard to the higher mental powers such as reasoning, for he observed that donkeys have a highly convoluted brain. Consequently, he thought that the cerebral convolutions could not be associated with intelligence. Instead, he identified the ventricles, rather than the cortex, as the source of such powers as reasoning. 32Galen enjoyed absolute authority for more than a millennium. It therefore comes as no surprise that the association of the ventricles with higher mental functions was elaborated in detail in the following centuries.

Nemesius: the formal attribution ofall mental functions to the ventricles

It was Nemesius ( c . 390), the bishop of Emesa (now Homs) in Syria, who developed the doctrine of the ventricular localization of all mental functions, rather than just the intellectual ones. Unlike Galen, he allocated perception and imagination to the two lateral ventricles (the anterior ventricles), placing intellectual abilities in the middle ventricle, reserving the posterior ventricles for memory. Hence the idea that imagination/perception, reasoning and memory are to be found in the lateral, third and fourth ventricles respectively. Nemesius claimed that this localization was based not on a whim but on solid evidence, for he states that

The most convincing proof is that derived from studying the activities of the various parts of the brain. If the front ventricles have suffered any kind of lesion, the senses are impaired but the faculty of intellect continues as before. It is when the middle of the brain is affected that the mind is deranged, but then the senses are left in possession of their natural function. If it is the cerebellum that is damaged, only loss of memory follows, while sensation and thought take no harm. But if the middle of the brain and the cerebellum share in the damage, in addition to the front ventricles, sensation, thought, and memory all founder together, with the result that the living subject is in danger of death. 33

In relation to the anterior ventricles, he states:

Now, as organs, the faculty of imagination 34has, first, the front lobes of the brain and the psychic spirit contained in them, then the nerves impregnated with psychic spirit that proceed from them, and, finally, the whole construction of the sense-organs. These organs of sense are five in number, but perception is one, and is an attribute of the soul. By means of the sense-organs, and their power of feeling, the soul takes knowledge of what goes on in them. 35

This localization of the various mental functions in the ventricles became known as the ventricular doctrine.

The soul taken as spiritual sub-stance rather than as first actuality

It is noteworthy that Nemesius conceived of the soul in very different terms from Aristotle and his followers. Nemesius, as a Christian, was more influenced by Neo-Platonism than by Aristotelian philosophy (he was attracted by the doctrine of the pre-existence of the soul, and also by metempsychosis). He did not conceive of the soul as the form of the body, but as a separate, indestructible spiritual substance, linked with the body in a ‘union without confusion’ in which the identity of each substance is fully preserved. Consequently, he did not attribute perception and cognition to the human being (i.e. to the whole animal), but rather to the soul. The attribution of psychological attributes to the soul of a living creature rather than to the living creature as a whole, deviates importantly from the Aristotelian conception. As we shall see, the tendency to explain how a living being perceives, thinks, feels emotions, etc. by reference to a constituent substance’ s or subordinate part of that being’ s perceiving, thinking, feeling emotions, etc. runs like a canker through the history of neuroscience to this very day.

Читать дальше
Тёмная тема
Сбросить

Интервал:

Закладка:

Сделать

Похожие книги на «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience»

Представляем Вашему вниманию похожие книги на «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience» списком для выбора. Мы отобрали схожую по названию и смыслу литературу в надежде предоставить читателям больше вариантов отыскать новые, интересные, ещё непрочитанные произведения.


Отзывы о книге «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience»

Обсуждение, отзывы о книге «Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience» и просто собственные мнения читателей. Оставьте ваши комментарии, напишите, что Вы думаете о произведении, его смысле или главных героях. Укажите что конкретно понравилось, а что нет, и почему Вы так считаете.

x